This article will be permanently flagged as inappropriate and made unaccessible to everyone. Are you certain this article is inappropriate? Excessive Violence Sexual Content Political / Social
Email Address:
Article Id: WHEBN0037531624 Reproduction Date:
Logical consequence (also entailment) is one of the most fundamental concepts in logic. It is the relationship between statements that holds true when one logically "follows from" one or more others. A valid logical argument is one in which the conclusions follow from its premises, and its conclusions are consequences of its premises. The philosophical analysis of logical consequence involves asking, 'in what sense does a conclusion follow from its premises?' and 'what does it mean for a conclusion to be a consequence of premises?'[1] All of philosophical logic can be thought of as providing accounts of the nature of logical consequence, as well as logical truth.[2]
Logical consequence is taken to be both necessary and formal with examples explicated using models and proofs.[1] A sentence is said to be a logical consequence of a set of sentences, for a given language, if and only if, using logic alone (i.e. without regard to any interpretations of the sentences) the sentence must be true if every sentence in the set were to be true.[3]
Logicians make precise accounts of logical consequence with respect to a given language \mathcal{L} by constructing a deductive system for \mathcal{L}, or by formalizing the intended semantics for \mathcal{L}. Alfred Tarski highlighted three salient features for which any adequate characterization of logical consequence needs to account: 1) that the logical consequence relation relies on the logical form of the sentences involved, 2) that the relation is a priori, i.e. it can be determined whether or not it holds without regard to sense experience, and 3) that the relation has a modal component.[3]
The most widely prevailing view on how to best account for logical consequence is to appeal to formality. This is to say that whether statements follow from one another logically depends on the structure or logical form of the statements without regard to the contents of that form.
Syntactic accounts of logical consequence rely on schemes using inference rules. For instance, we can express the logical form of a valid argument as "All A are B. All C are A. Therefore, All C are B." This argument is formally valid, because every instance of arguments constructed using this scheme are valid.
This is in contrast to an argument like "Fred is Mike's brother's son. Therefore Fred is Mike's nephew." Since this argument depends on the meanings of the words "brother", "son", and "nephew", the statement "Fred is Mike's nephew" is a so-called material consequence of "Fred is Mike's brother's son," not a formal consequence. A formal consequence must be true in all cases, however this is an incomplete definition of formal consequence, since even the argument "P is Q's brother's son, therefore P is Q's nephew" is valid in all cases, but is not a formal argument.[1]
If you know that Q follows logically from P no information about the possible interpretations of P or Q will affect that knowledge. Our knowledge that Q is a logical consequence of P cannot be influenced by empirical knowledge.[1] Deductively valid arguments can be known to be so without recourse to experience, so they must be knowable a priori.[1] However, formality alone does not guarantee that logical consequence is not influenced by empirical knowledge. So the a priori property of logical consequence is considered to be independent of formality.[1]
The two prevailing techniques for providing accounts of logical consequence involve expressing the concept in terms of proofs and via models. The study of the syntactic consequence (of a logic) is called (its) proof theory whereas the study of (its) semantic consequence is called (its) model theory.[4]
A formula A is a syntactic consequence[5][6][7][8] within some formal system \mathcal{FS} of a set \Gamma of formulas if there is a formal proof in \mathcal{FS} of A from the set \Gamma.
Syntactic consequence does not depend on any interpretation of the formal system.[9]
A formula A is a semantic consequence within some formal system \mathcal{FS} of a set of statements \Gamma
if and only if there is no model \mathcal{I} in which all members of \Gamma are true and A is false.[10] Or, in other words, the set of the interpretations that make all members of \Gamma true is a subset of the set of the interpretations that make A true.
Modal accounts of logical consequence are variations on the following basic idea:
Alternatively (and, most would say, equivalently):
Such accounts are called "modal" because they appeal to the modal notions of logical necessity and logical possibility. 'It is necessary that' is often expressed as a universal quantifier over possible worlds, so that the accounts above translate as:
Consider the modal account in terms of the argument given as an example above:
The conclusion is a logical consequence of the premises because we can't imagine a possible world where (a) all frogs are green; (b) Kermit is a frog; and (c) Kermit is not green.
Modal-formal accounts of logical consequence combine the modal and formal accounts above, yielding variations on the following basic idea:
The accounts considered above are all "truth-preservational," in that they all assume that the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from true premises to an untrue conclusion. As an alternative, some have proposed "warrant-preservational" accounts, according to which the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from justifiably assertible premises to a conclusion that is not justifiably assertible. This is (roughly) the account favored by intuitionists such as Michael Dummett.
The accounts discussed above all yield monotonic consequence relations, i.e. ones such that if A is a consequence of \Gamma, then A is a consequence of any superset of \Gamma. It is also possible to specify non-monotonic consequence relations to capture the idea that, e.g., 'Tweety can fly' is a logical consequence of
but not of
For more on this, see Belief revision#Non-monotonic inference relation.
Epistemology, Computer science, Philosophy, Aesthetics, Metaphysics
Logic, Truth, Philosophical logic, Logical consequence, Fact
Set theory, Logic, Model theory, Mathematics, Foundations of mathematics
Axiom of choice, Mathematical logic, Category theory, Mathematics, Foundations of mathematics
Logic, Rhetoric, Classical logic, Truth, Non-classical logic
Aristotle, Logical consequence, Prior Analytics, Deductive reasoning, Mathematical logic
Logic, Mathematical logic, String (computer science), Semantics, Set theory
Predicate logic, Mathematical logic, Set theory, Modus ponens, Formal system